Volcanic eruption, Ngauruhoe, New Zealand. Photo from National Geophysical Data Center (US).

Statistical laws

I have tried to show, in the previous two chapters, that determinism and free will are compatible, that one need not postulate a breakdown of determinism to accommodate free will. I have tried to show that the problem comes about through a mistaken conception of what physical laws are; the solution to the problem does not require abandoning Determinism, but neither does it require embracing Determinism.
    Freed of the enticement of warranting indeterminism to solve the free-will problem, we can now go about investigating the matter of probabilistic laws in a dispassionate way. At the very least, the solutions to the weighty problems of free will and moral responsibility will not hang in the balance.
    The Copenhagen interpretation (1927) of quantum mechanics … historically served as the catalyst for the contemporary debate about the status of statistical laws. That the debate should derive its principal impetus from physics is unfortunate from the point of view of intellectual history. For it bolsters the belief that the natural sciences are somehow more fundamental than the social sciences and that the “true” nature of physical laws is to be learned from what physics and chemistry reveal, rather than from such sciences as economics and/or sociology. Certainly, the view still prevails that the “laws” of sociology are but the logical consequences of the “fundamental” laws of physics and chemistry. Such a view carries the corollary that, were the “laws” of sociology, economics and so on to be statistical rather than universal, this fact would not be decisive, or even for that matter particularly relevant, in answering the question of whether any “real” physical laws are statistical or whether all physical laws are – without exception – universal. “Real” laws, in this view, are the preserve of physics, and it is to physics and physics alone that one must turn to answer questions of whether “real” laws are statistical.
    This way of approaching the question of whether physical laws can be statistical makes it look as if what were at issue were an empirical question, as if it were a matter to be settled in the physicists’ laboratories whether physical laws might have a certain property. But surely this is a mistake. To proceed in the manner imagined, one would have to have an independent way of recognizing what a physical law is, and then one would check to see whether any members of this class were statistical rather than universal. We have only to put the matter this way to see immediately that the question is not empirical but conceptual. It falls to us to decide whether, and if so under what circumstances, we might want to allow that a statistical proposition is to be regarded as a physical law. Certainly, it is an empirical matter to discover which of a certain class of contrary propositions, of potential laws, is in fact a law; but to decide what the criteria are by which a proposition comes to be in this class of candidates for lawfulness in a conceptual problem.
    What “laws” certain sciences – for example, sociology, economics, pharmacology, linguistics – adduce are nearly always statistical. Is this because the “real” laws are universal, but incapable of explicit formulation, perhaps because of the enormous number of variables, the unethicalness of performing controlled social-scientific experiments, prohibitions of cost, irreproducibility of initial conditions, etc? Or might it be that the “real” underlying laws of social events are genuinely statistical?
    If some physical laws are statistical, then it logically follows that some statistical propositions are physical laws. I want to go considerably further. I want, now, to argue that not just some, but all statistical propositions that satisfy all other requirements for physical lawfulness – being true, contingent, conditional, and purely descriptive in their nonlogical and nonmathematical terms – are physical laws.

Swartz, Norman. The Concept of Physical Law, Cambridge University Press, 1985, pp. 171-173